• Nenhum resultado encontrado

A Characterization of Principal Congruences of De Morgan Algebras and its Applications

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "A Characterization of Principal Congruences of De Morgan Algebras and its Applications"

Copied!
9
0
0

Texto

(1)

©NQrth-Holland Publishing Company, 1980

A CHARACTERIZATION OF PRINCIPAL CONGRUENCES OF DE MORGAN ALGEBRAS AND ITS APPLICATIONS

H.P. Sankappanavall.

ABSTRACT. In this paper a characterization of prin-cipal congruences of De Morgan algebras is given and from it we derive that the variety of De Morgan alge-bras has DPC and CEP. The characterization is then appl ied to give a new proof of Kalman's characteriza-tion of subdirectly irreducibles in this variety and thus to obtain the representation theorem for De Morgan algebras first proved by Kalman and independently, usingtopological methods, by 8ialynicki- Bi rula and Rasiowa. From this representation it is deduced that finite De Morgan algebras are not the only ones wi th Boolean congruence lattices. Finally it is shown that the compact elements in the congruence lattice of a De Morgan algebra form a Boolean sublattice.

§1. INTRODUCTION,

Principal congruences have turned out to be a useful tool, especially after the publication of Day 1971, in obtaining some interesting information about a given variety (equational class) of algebras. For example, the "equational" char-acterization of principal congruences of distributive lattices - first given by Gratzer and Schmidt (see Gratzer 1971, Theorem 3, p. 87) - has been used, among other things, to characterize subdirect irreducibility (Example 3 in Gratzer 1971); and it also implies that the variety of distributive lattices has definable prin-cipal congruences(DPC) (see §4 below for definition) and has congruence extension property (CEP). (This is immediate via Day 1971.) Lasker 1973 found a similar characterization in the case of distributive pseudo-complemented lattices and used it to deduce CEP and OPC. Recently we observed in Sankappanavar 197+ b that his characterization could also be used to give a very simple proof of the characteri-zation by Lakser (see Gratzer 1971, Theorem 7, p. 178) of subdirectly irreducible distributive pseudocomplemented lattices. To cite still another example, princi-ple congruences of pseudo-comprinci-plemented semilattices are characterized in Sankappa-navar 197+ a and DPC and CEP are deduced; moreover, this characterization is applied in Sankappanavar 197+ b to give a new direct proof of a result, due 'to Jones, characterizing subdirectly irreducible ones.

In this paper a characterization of principal congru~nces of De Morgan alge-bras is given. From this it follows that the variety of De Morgan algealge-bras has DPe and CEP. This characterization is then applied to give a new proof of Kal-man's characterization of subdirectly irreducibles in this variety and thus to ob-tain the representation theorem for De Morgan algebras first proved by Kalman and later, using topological methods, by Bialynicki-Birula and Rasiowa. From this it

(2)

is deduced that finite De Morgan algebras are the only ones with Boolean congru-ence lattices. Finally it is shown that the compact elements in the congruence lattice of a De Morgan algebra form a Boolean sUblattice.

Recall that a De Morgan algebra is an algebra (Ai 1\, V, 'V, 0, I> of type (2,2,1,0,0> such that (Ai1\,V,0,1) is a bounded distributive lattice satis-fying the identities 'V'V x = x and "'(xVy) = 'VX1\-vIf. (We refer to -vas the De Morgan negation.)t For a systematic study of these algebras see Ba1bes and Dwinger 1974 and Rasiowa 1974. Throughout this paper A denotes an arbitrary De Morgan algebra. For the notation we refer the reader to Balbes and Dwinger 1974 and Gratzer 1971. We let O(a,b) and 0Lat(a,b) denote respectively the princi-pal De Morgan algebra congruence and the principrinci-pal lattice congruence on A gene-rated by the pair (a,b) in AxA. BIAl denotes the set of complemented ele-ments of A, while C(A) consi sts of those elements a of A such that the Bool-ean complement a' in A coincides with the De Morgan negation 'Va. It is clear that C{A) c B(A); and the equality holds iff A is a Boolean algebra. Finally we let Con-A to denote the congruence lattice of A and recall that it is a dis-tributive algebraic lattice.

§ 2. PRINCIPAL CONGRUENCES,

In this section we shall give a characterization of principal congruences of a De Morgan algebra. The following Lemma - whose proof is straightforward - is cru-cial for the rest of the paper.

LEMMA 2.1. LeX: a,bE A wUh 0.<;; b. Then

°

(a,b) = 0Lat(a,b) V 0Lat('Vb, 'Va).

THEOREM 2.2. LeX: a,b E A .6u.c.h that it -c b. FOJt x,lf .£n A, (x, If] E

°

(a,b) .£nn .the. noUow.£ng .£deYJ..t.U.£e.6 Me tJtu.e .£/1 A :

1) xl\al\'Vb=lfl\al\'Vb 2) (xt\a)V'Va = (yt\a) V 'Va

3) (xVb)t\.7vb= (yVb)1\ 'Vb

4) xVbV'Va=yVbV"'a,

OJi. eqiJ..£valel'Lti.y the .£de.YJ..t.U.£e.6 1), 2'). 3') and 4) Me tJtu.e.£n A, wheJte

2') (xV'Va)l\a=(yV'Va)l\a, and

3') (xl\'Vb)Vb (yl\'Vb)Vb

PROOF. Let us denote by [a] the element in the distributive lattice A/OLat('Vb, 'Va) corresponding to an element a EA. Then by Lemma 2.1 we have t These algebras were first studied in Kalman 1958 (actually in his thesis 1955)

(but without 0 and 1) as a common abstraction of Boolean algebras and lattice-ordered groups and by Bialynicki-Birula and Rasiowa under the name of quasi-Boolean algebras. These algebras are related to constructive logic with strong negation.

(3)

for x,yE A ,

(x,y) E(J(a,b) iff ([ xl, [yl) E (JLat([al ,[bl) in A/(JLat('Vb, 'Va) iff [xl /\ [a] = [yl /\ [a] and [xl V [bl = [yl V [b] iff (x A«, y/\a) E (JLat('Vb,'Va) and (x Vo, yVb)EOLat('Vb,'Va) iff the identities 1)- 4) are true in A.

Similarly by considering A/(JLat(a,b) it is readily seen that (x,y) E (J (a,b)

iff 1), 2'), 3') and 4) hold in A and thus the proof is complete.

-COROLLARY 2.3. Let x,y,aE A. Then:the o0.uow'<'ng C.OYlciU{.OI1J.l Me eqtUva-lent:

a) (x,y) E

e

(a, 1)

b) (x/\a) V 'Va = (y/\a) V 'V a c) (xV'Va)/\ 11.= (yV 'Va)/\a.

IYl pantic.~ oO~ a E C(A) wehave (x,y) E

e

la, 1) '<'66 x /\ 11.= Y/\a '<'06

xV'Va = yV'Va.

(We just remark here that this corollary includes the well-known characteriza-tion of principal congruences of Boolean algebras.)

COROLLARY 2.4. Le.t aE A. TheYl (J(a,a V 'Va) =(JLat(a, aV 'Va). IYl otheJl. WMM, (x,y) E (J(a, aV 'V a) '<'60 x /\a = y /\ a aYld xVa V 'Va = yVaV 'V a.

IYl pMtiC.u1.M,'<'O a"'Va :theYl (x,y) E

e

(a, 'Va) '<'00 x /\ a = y /\ a aYld xV'Va=yV'Va.

PROOF. Observe ('V(aV'Va), 'Va) E(JLat(a,

aV'Va).-COROLLARY 2.5. Let aE A. TheYl:the o0.uOW'<'Ylg Me eqtUvalent.

i ) Thelattic.e c.oYlgitUeYlc.e (JLat(a, 1) OYl A ..{.o aVe MoJtgan algebM C.OYlg~u.­ enc.eOyl A,

ti ) 'Va..{.o:the BooleaYl c.omplement 00 a '<'yl A k.e. 'Va E C(A».

PROOF. From i) and ('Va, 0) E (J(a., 1) we see that ('Va.,O)E (JLat(a., 1) which implies "va /\ a =0, thus yielding ii). On the other hand, from i i ) and Corollary 2.3 we have ('Va, 0) E eLat(a, 1), thus i) is immediate.

-Thus the property i) in the above corollary is characteristic of Boolean alge-bras among De Morgan algealge-bras. It also follows from the preceding corollary that the condition (2) of Lemma 4.3 in eignoli 1975 can be improved to: For every aE B(A) the lattice congruence (JLat(a, 1) is also a De Morgan algebra congru-ence on A.

(4)

Following Baldwin and Berman 1975 we say that a variety V has de6.i.nablepJUn-upal congftuence.o (DPC) iff there is a formula ¢(u, v, ft,.6) in the first order language of V so that for all AE V and a, b, c, dE A, ¢!c,d,a,bl holds in

A iff (c,d) EO(a,b). Regarding the usefulness of DPC and varieties with DPC the reader may refer to, for example, Baldwin and Berman 1975, McKenzie 1978, Gratzer 1971, Lakser 1973 and Sankappanavar 197+ b.

Thus the following Theorem is immediate from Theorem 2.2. THEOR EM 3.1. The vaiUety 06 Ve MOftgM algebftM has DPC.

Day 1972 proved that if an equational class has the property that in each of its members the condition (x,y) EO(a,b) is determined by a set of equations in-volving only x,y,a,b then the congruence extension property (see Gratzer 1971 for definition) holds in that class. In the case of De Morgan algebras the reader can easily write down such equations using our Theorem 2.2 for x, y, a, bin A (where a, b are not necessarily comparable). Thus we have

THEOREM 3.2. The vaiUettj 06Pe MOJtgan algebftM has the congJtu.ence exten.6-<-on pM pe.Jtty•

It may be remarked here that Theorems 3.1 and 3.2 could be obtained by more involved methods. For example Theorem 3.2 is a consequence of results in eigno1i 1975 and Banaschewski 1969 and then an existential proof of Theorem 3.1 is ob-tained from Theorem 3.2 and the (known) fact that every finitely generated De Mor-gan algebra is finite, together with a result in Baldwin and Berman 1975, while our proof gives an explicit defining formula.

SUBDIRECTLY IRREDUCIBLE DE MORGAN ALGEBRAS,

Kalman 1958 characterized the subdirectly irreducible De Morgan algebras and thereby obtained the complete description of the lattice of subvarieties of the variety of De Morgan algebras and a representation theorem. Later, using topolog-ical methods Bialynicki-Birula and Rasiowa 1958 (see also Ba1bes and Dwinger 1974 obtained the same representation theorem.

We shall now apply Theorem 2.2 to give new proofs of these results. For this we need the following observation.

LEMMA 3.3. Let A be aVe Moftgan algebJta 06hugh;{:. ;;.3 and w-<.th IC(A)j =2. Then theM -i..6 an element a1= 0 -<-11 A .6uch that a <"'a.

PROOF. We may suppose that there are elements xl' x2 in A such that 0 < Xl < x2 < 1. We may further assume that each of "'Xl and "'x2 is incomparable with each of Xl and x2 since in all other cases the Lemma is trivially veri-fied. Now set a = (XlV", x2) /\ x2 /\ '" Xl and we claim that a has all the de-sired properties. Observe that '"a = Xl V", x2V ('" Xl /\ x2) and hence a <v«, furthermore if a = '"a then Xl V-vx2=x2 /\ '" Xl and hence '" x2 ... x2 whi ch contradicts our supposition and thus a<'Va. Finally if a = 0 then noting

that a = (Xl /\ 'V Xl) V ('Vx2 /\ X2) we see that Xl /\ 'V Xl = 0 and hence Xl E C(A} which is a contradiction to the hypothesis. Thus our claim is proved and

(5)

hence the lemma ••

The following three De Morgan algebras 2, 3 and 4 given in figure I, where

'Va =a, 'Vb=b and 'V c =c , playa very special role in the theory of De

Mor-gan algebras. We now apply our results to give a simple proof of Kalman's result

mentioned earlier. Observe that B(4) {O,b, c , l} while C(4) = {O,I} .

2 a b

0

c 0 0 3 4 (Figure 1)

THEOREM 3.4. (Kalman 1958) Lu A be non-bUv,£.aL Then the 60tlow'£'ng~e

equ.-i.vatent:

1) A .{.6 ,/>.{mp.te •

2) A .{.6 ./>ubcUtteclilf .{.Meduub.te •

3) A .{.6 06hught <3 and CIA) {O,1 } 4) A .{.6 utheJt 2 ott 3 ott 4.

PROOF. 2)" 3) is the only non-trivial implication, and we shall prove it

here. Suppose A is subdirectly irreducible. If CIA) has an element different

from 0 and 1 then from Corollary 2.5 it follows that O(b, 1) A e('Vb,l) = L\ (the

least element in Con A), which is a contradiction and hence CIA) = {O,l}. Next

suppose the height of A~ 3. Then by the preceding Lemma there is an element a

in A such that a <'Va and a

*

O. But then from Corollaries 2.3 and 2.4 it

follows that e(a, 'Va) A e('Va, 1) = L\ which is again a contradiction and so the

height of A is less than 3. Thus (3) is true and the theorem is proved. •

In vie~1 of the famous Birkhoff's theorem the following corollaries are

immedi-ate. Let VIA) denote the variety generated by A.

COROLLARY 3.5. EveJtlj 11On-bUv,£.at DeMOItgan atgebJta A .{.6 a ./>ubcUJtect

pttod-uct 06 ./>.{mp.tu [vz.z, 2, 3 and 4).

COROLLARY 3.G. (Kalrnan 1958; Bialynicki-Birula and Rasiowa 1957) A .{.6 a

./>ubcttgebJta 06 a cUttect poweJt 06 4.

COROLLARY 3.7. (Kalman 1958) The ffittice 06 ./>ubvaJt,{.eU.u 06 De Ilo"csan

a.t-gebJta-6.{.6 (( C,-element chun COI'LO.{.6;(;,{.llg o~ V(I) (ttUv-<.a.t r,xgebtta-6) , V 2) 1800,[-ea;,atfJebtLa-6) , V13) 1M-called K.teeneatgebJta-6) and V(4) lall DeMOItgan atge-bJta-6 ) •

Finally combining Corollary 3.4 with Day 1972, Theorem 4.1, one readily

(6)

an explicit characterization of injectives.

COROLLARY 3.8. (Cignoli 1975) V(4) and Ii (3) have. e.nvugL inje.Uive..6 and "he.nee. have. the. wnalgamation P40P~Y.

CONGRUENCE LATTICES,

We shall now apply our previous results to obtain some information about the structure of congruence lattices. We have the following theorem characterizing the De Morgan algebras with Boolean congruence lattices.

THEOREM 3.8. Con Ai.6 Boole.an

.£66

A

u

MniA.e.

PROOF, Since A is semisimple, from a result of Tanaka 1952 (or see Burris 1975 , Corollary 2.6) it follows that Con A is a Boolean lattice iff any two e-lements of A are equal on all but finitely many factors, and the latter is true iff A is finite ••

In the rest of the paper our concern is to show that the compact elements in Con A form a Boolean sublattice of Con A. It is well-known that in a distribu-tive lattice the meet of two principal congruences is a principal congruence (see Lakser 1973 for example). In fact, if a';;; b "and e';;;d then /}Lat (a, b) II

/}Lat(e,d)

=

IJLat(b II

d

II (aV e),

b

II

d).

However, in a De Morgan algebra this property may not hold in general, but we still have the following useful informa-tion.

LEMt1A 3.9. Let a,b,e,dE A w.{;th a';;; band e';;; d. The.n

/}(a,b) IIIJfe,dl =B(aVe, aVeV (blld))

v e

(aV'Vd,aV'VdV (bll'Ve)l. PROOF, Using Lemma 2.1 and distributivity of ConA we have

I)(a,b) /\ I)fe,d) = [I)Lat(a,bl V/}Lat('Vb,'Va)]/\ [I)Latfe,d) V I)Lat ('Vd, 'Ve)] = [I)Lat[a,bl MLatfe,d)] V [I)Lat[a,bl /\ I)Lat ('Vd, 'Ve)]

Recall that IJ Lat(xIIy, x) =BLat(Y, x Vy), and thus we have

(7)

=O(aVe, av c.v (bAd)) VO[aV < d ; aV 'Vd V(bA 'Ve)). Thus the Lemma is proved. •

LEMMA 3.10. EveJtlj pJUnc..tpal eon9'tUenee on A hM a complement wlUeh .u, eom-pact~n Con A. In nact~n a,b E A and a ~ b then

e(a,bJ' = 1)('VaVb,l) V elbA»b,'Vb) VI) ['Va, 'VaVa). PROOF. Observe that

[O,'VbAa) E 1)['VaVb, 1), ('VbAa,'VbAb) E I)(a,b), ('VbAb, 'Vb) E I) (bA 'Vb, 'Vb), ('Vb, 'Va) E I) (a,b) ,

('Va, 'Va Va)E I) ('Va,'Va Va) , ('Vavo ,'Va Vb) EO (a,b) and ( 'VaVb,1 J E I) ('VaVb,1) •

Thus if ~ denotes the congruence on the right side of the above equation then we just observed that I) (a,b) V9>=1)(0, 1). Finally using the previous Lemma it is straightforward to verify that I)(a,b) II~ =~. •

The following theorem reveals the nice structure of congruence lattices of De Morgan algebras.

THEOREM 3.11. CQn A -U a d-UtJUbu.Uve algebtuUc .ea.:t:Ucewho.oe eompact e1.e-merLt6

n

0!U11 a Boolean .6U.b.ea.:t:Uee.

PROOF, From Lemma 3.9 and distributivity of Con A it readily follows that the meet of compact elements is compact in Con A and thus the compact elements in Con A form a sublattice. Finally the fact that this sub1attice is Boo1 ean follows from Lemma 3.10, thus the proof is complete. •

Finally we remark that in view of Theorem 3.8 the converse to the above theo· rem is true if A is finite, however it is not known if it holds in general.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENT,

The author would like to thank the organizing committee of the Fourth Lati n-American Symposium on Mathematical Logic for inviting him to participate in the Symposium. The final version of this paper was written during January 1979 when the author was visiting the Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Water-loo, WaterWater-loo, Ontario, Canada, to whom the author is grateful. Finally he is spe-cially thankful to Professor Stanley Burris who kindly invited the author to pre· sent the results of this paper in his Logic Seminar and who has always been the source of inspiration to the author.

(8)

REFERENCES,

R. Balbes and P. Dwinger

1974 Distributive Lattices, University of Missouri Press, Columbia. J. Baldwin and J.T. Berman

1975 The. numbeJt 06-6ubcUAe.c.:te.y -Uute.duub.te. a.l.ge.b!tfu\ -<.n a vcvUuy, Alg. Univ. vol. 5, pp. 379 - 389.

B. Banaschewski

1969 Inje.c.UvUy ande.Me.nt:<.a.l. e.xt:e.n-6-<'0n-6 -<.n e.qu.a.t.i.onal. c1.a.-6M-6 06 a.l.ge.b!tfu\ , Proceedings of the Conference in Universal Algebra, Queen's University, Kingston.

A. Bialynicki - Birula and H. Rasiowa

1957 On the. 4e.p4e.-6e.nt~on 06 qu.a-6-i.-Boo.te.an a.l.ge.b4a-6, Bull. Acad. Pol. Sci. CI. III 5, pp, 259 - 261.

1958 On c.on-6t4u.c.tib.te. 6a.l.-6Uy -<.n the. C.On-6t4uc.Uve. .tog-<.c. wUh -6t4ong ne.g~on, Colloq. r~ath. vol • 6, pp, 287 - 310.

S. Burris

1975 Se.paJtating -6W -<.n modu..f.aJI. J'.a.;t;Uc.e.-6 w-<.th appUc.a..ti.on-6 to c.ong4u.e.nc.e.

.eat-tic.e.-6, Alg. Univ. vol , 5, pp. 213 - 223.

R. Cignoli

1975 Inje.c.Uve. De. M04gan and Kte.e.ne. alge.b!tfu\, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. vol. 47. pp, 269·278.

1978 The. J'.a.;t;Uce. 06 g.toba..t -6e.c.UOn-6 06 -6heave.-6 06 cha.-i.n-6 oveJt Boolean -6paCe.-6,

Alg. Univ. vol. 8, pp, 357 - 373. A. Day

1971 Anote. on the. cong4ue.nc.e. e.xt:en-6-i.on p40pe.4ty, Alg. Univ. vol. 1, pp. 234-235.

1972 Inje.c.UvUy -<.n e.qu.a.tiona..t c.!a.-6-6e.-6 06 alge.b!tfu\, Can. J. Math. vol. 24, pp. 209 - 220.

G. Gratzer

1971 Lattice Theory: First concepts and distributive lattices, Freeman, San Francisco.

J. Kalman

(9)

H. Lakser

1973 PJUYLUpal COYLgllUeYLCe..6 06 p.6cudocomptemeYLted .6em.Ua.:tt-<:Ce..6, Proc. Amer.Math. Soc., vol. 37, pp , 32 - 36.

R. McKenzie

1978 P~ pJUmal v~etie..6: A.6tudy 06 6~YLite axiom~zab~y aYLd de6~YLabte

pJUYLUpal cOYLgllUeYLce..6 ~YL .e.oca.lty MYLite v~etie..6, Alg. Univ. vol. 8, pp, 336 - 348.

H. Rasiowa

1974 An algebraic approach to non-classical logics, North-Ho11 and , Amsterdam.

H.P. Sankappanavar

197+a PJUYLUpal COYLgltueYLCe..6 06 p.6eudocomptemeYLted -6em.Ua.:tt-<:Ce..6 a.YLd COYLgllUeYLce

exteYL-6~OYL pltope!tty, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. (to appear).

197+ b Remaltfu, OYL-6ub~ec.ily .uur.eduubte p-6eudocomptemeYLted -6em.Ua.:tt-<:Ce..6 aYLd

~tM.bu.Uve p-6eudocomp.e.emeYLted .e.a.:tt<.c.e..6. (Preprint). T. Tanaka

1952 CaYLo~c.al -6ub~ec.t 6ac.toJUz~oYL 06 ta.:tt.i.Ce..6, J. Sci. Hiroshima Univ.Ser. A-I, vol. 16, pp, 239 - 246.

Instituto de Matematica Universidade Federal da Bahia Salvador, Bahia, Brazil.

Department of Pure Mathematics University of Waterloo Waterloo, Ontario, Canada.

Referências

Documentos relacionados

Este artigo discute o filme Voar é com os pássaros (1971) do diretor norte-americano Robert Altman fazendo uma reflexão sobre as confluências entre as inovações da geração de

“adquirir, tratar, tornar acessíveis e disseminar os recursos de informação, mas também enriquecer, conservar e preservar as colecções bibliográficas que integram o

Representar este Oriente, (re)construí-lo discursivamente, era revivê-lo, era transportar para as terras de África uma glória que ficou na centúria de quinhentos. Muito

Afinal, se o marido, por qualquer circunstância, não puder assum ir a direção da Família, a lei reconhece à mulher aptidão para ficar com os poderes de chefia, substituição que

Dessa forma, o direito à vida, na jurisprudência da Corte, relaciona-se intrinsecamente com os direitos econômicos, sociais e culturais, sendo atribuída ao Estado uma função

processo se afigura como um dos mais relevantes, uma vez que, por hipótese, temos que ele subjaz a todo mecanismo de derivação frasal. Quando se considera a ocorrência do fenômeno

Na hepatite B, as enzimas hepáticas têm valores menores tanto para quem toma quanto para os que não tomam café comparados ao vírus C, porém os dados foram estatisticamente

Because the artistic education of people is, in many cases, better developed than their grasp of science, it would appear more useful to employ a metaphorical description of the